State Redistricting Law: Stephenson v. Bartlett and Judicial Promotion of Electoral Competition

This Note attempts to answer the question, “What can state courts do to solve problems in the legislative redistricting process?” To answer this question, the Note examines one recent case from the North Carolina Supreme Court, Stephenson v. Bartlett. At the time the suit was filed, the North Carolina redistricting process was already subject to many state and federal constitutional restraints, as well as the federal statutory restraints of the Voting Rights Act. Relying on a dubious interpretation of the state constitution’s equal protection clause and an elevation of “traditional redistricting principles” to the level of a constitutional mandate, the North Carolina Supreme Court took the opportunity to create even more restraints on legislative redistricting process. Whitaker examines possible justifications for the opinion, and after rejecting textualist, purposivist and partisan political explanations, explains the opinion as an attempt by the judiciary to increase electoral competition by reducing the discretion of the state legislature over redistricting.

Halpin on Dworkin’s Fallacy: A Surreply

In my recent essay, Dworkin’s Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can’t Teach Us about the Law, 89 Va. L. Rev. 1897 (2003), I argued that a particular confusion between linguistic and legal practices – evident most notably in the work of Ronald Dworkin – causes legal theorists to misderive jurisprudential conclusions from semantic premises. Because much, if not most, jurisprudential interest in the philosophy of language is motivated by Dworkin’s fallacy, I argued that the philosophy of language does not generally have jurisprudential consequences. But in the conclusion to my essay I identified three areas where Dworkin’s fallacy does not apply and the philosophy of language has genuine, albeit very limited, consequences for the philosophy of law. 

Halpin argues that I neglected a number of important connections between the two disciplines. But the connections Halpin describes are in fact those that I identified as genuine in the conclusion to my essay. What is more, Halpin appears to agree with me that these connections, although genuine, are very limited, in the sense that they yield few substantive jurisprudential consequences. Halpin sees a disagreement between us on these matters only because he misunderstands the confusion of linguistic and legal practices at issue in Dworkin’s fallacy.

But Halpin does argue for a connection between the philosophies of language and law that is different from those I entertained in my essay. I was interested in whether the philosophy of language can yield conclusions in the philosophy of law. Halpin appears to agree with me that it cannot. But Halpin argues that the philosophy of law can yield conclusions in the philosophy of language. Although Halpin’s argument here is suggestive, it is insufficiently detailed to allow me to come to a firm conclusion about its merits.

In my essay I offered Dennis Patterson’s legal theory, with Dworkin’s, as examples of Dworkin’s fallacy in action. Halpin argues that Patterson’s theory does not suffer from Dworkin’s fallacy. I end my response to Halpin with a defense of my critique of Patterson, by expanding what was admittedly a compressed argument in the original. 

Or, Even, What the Law Can Teach The Philosophy of Language: A Response to Green’s Dworkin’s Fallacy

This essay is a response to the important central theme of Michael Green’s recent article, Dworkin’s Fallacy, or What the Philosophy of Language Can’t Teach Us about the Law, 89 Va. L. Rev. 1897 (2003), which considers the relationship between the philosophy of language and the philosophy of law. Green argues forcefully that a number of theorists with quite different viewpoints commonly maintain a connection between the two which turns out to be unfounded. It is accepted that it is wrong to assume such a connection, but it is suggested that Green has failed to recognise the connection that can be established between the two disciplines due to the particular way in which law as a practice uses words.

The reasons given by Green for seeking to maintain a distinction between ordinary language practice and the language practice of the law are considered and rejected in part I of the essay. The general conclusion is reached that, irrespective of which position is adopted in the philosophy of law, at the point of judgment the philosophy of law and the philosophy of language are inextricably linked in being concerned to account for the same practice.

Part II of the essay considers the basic issues for the philosophy of language addressed in Green’s article, which are concerned with the search for the mechanism which links a particular meaning to a word. One reading of Wittgenstein’s rule skepticism, supported by Dennis Patterson, is to reject the existence of any mechanism interrupting the direct connection between the capacity we possess in our language practice and the capacity we possess in the practice to which our language refers. Patterson provides another target for Green’s allegation that theorists who take a position in the philosophy of law from their position in the philosophy of language are committing a fallacy. However, it is pointed out that within the Patterson-Wittgenstein position, there is no possibility of moving from one position to the other since both positions are already necessarily connected.

The remaining discussion in Part II then explores the apparently common connection between law and language established within the practice of judgment and within the general view of the nature of language favoured in Patterson’s reading of Wittgenstein. It is argued that Wittgenstein’s philosophical method may maintain a connection between law and language, and the positions adopted within their respective philosophies, but is incapable of resolving the controversy between competing views of how law/”law” should be understood. By contrast, the practice of judgment is used precisely to resolve controversy. Although this judgment is concerned primarily with a specific part of the law, its significance extends to how we regard the philosophical endeavours that need to provide an account of it. This provides lessons for both the philosophy of language and the philosophy of law.